Document Type : Original Article

Author

PhD in Islamic Philosophy and Theology, Imam Khomeini International University, Qazvin, Iran.

Abstract

In his Copernican revolution, Kant changed the centrality of cognition from the external world to the subject. In this way, human mental structure provides the context of experience; nd based on that, he acquires aesthetic and imaginary knowledge and finally reaches the understanding of the external world. Although Kant proposes this theory and goes as far as the schematism by imagination, it seems that his views are confused in explaining categories as pure concepts that are completely independent of experience, sense and time. According to Kant's doctrine, every concept and therefore categories must be referred to an intuition. But on the one hand, if categories are returned to sense and experience in any way, then they are not pure concepts of understanding; Although Kant does not accept it, he cannot explain his opinion successfully; On the other hand, if categories are pure and beyond experience and sense, then they must be referred to something; And Kant refers them to the "objective in general" intuition; But in this case, he is caught in the transcendental object; Especially, the characteristics that Kant enumerates for the "object in general" create the suspicion that the understanding perceives the categories with intellectual intuition from the "object in general" or in other words from "Being".

Keywords

Main Subjects

ابن‌سینا (1404ق). الشفاء، الهیات. قم: کتابخانة آیت‌الله مرعشی نجفی.##
ایلخانی، محمد (1382). تاریخ فلسفه در قرون وسطی و رنسانس. تهران: سمت.##
عبدالکریمی، بیژن (1381). هایدگر و استعلا؛ شرحی بر تفسیر هایدگر از کانت. تهران: نقد فرهنگ.##
فتح طاهری، علی؛ قنبرلو، زینب (1392). «بررسی و نقد استنتاج متافیزیکی مقولات در فلسفه کانت». فصلنامه ذهن. شمارة 56، ص140ـ115.##
کاپلستون، فردریک (1375). تاریخ فلسفه، ج6: از ولف تا کانت. ترجمۀ اسماعیل سعادت و منوچهر بزرگمهر. تهران: علمی و فرهنگی.##
کانت، ایمانوئل (1383). سنجش خرد ناب. ترجمة میرشمس­الدین ادیب­سلطانی. تهران: امیرکبیر.##
کورنر، اشتفان (1380). فلسفۀ کانت. ترجمۀ عزت‌اله فولادوند. تهران: خوارزمی.##
ملاصدرا، (1383) الحکمة المتعالیة فی الأسفار الأربعة، ج1. تصحیح غلامرضا اعوانی. تهران: بنیاد حکمت اسلامی صدرا.##
وال، ژان (1380). بحث در مابعدالطبیعه. ترجمۀ یحیی مهدوی و همکاران. تهران: خوارزمی.##
Allison, H. E. (1986). Kant's transcendental idealism. New Haven and London: Yale University press##
Bird, G. (2006). A companion to Kant. Wiley-Blackwell.##
Ewing A. C. (1938). A short commentary on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Chicago: the University of Chicago press, ##
Heidegger, M. (1997). Phenomenological interpretation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. trans. by P. Emad & K. Maly. Indiana##
Heidegger, M. (1999). On the being and conception of Φύσις in Aristotle's Physics B, 1. trans. by T. Sheehan. Man and World. vol. 9, no. 3, pp. 219-279.##
Kant, I. (1929). Critique of pure reason. trans. by Norman Kemp Smith. London: MacMillan.##
Kant, I. (1992). Lectures on Logic. part17, The Jasche logic. trans. by M. Young. Cambridge University press.##
Kant, I. (1997). Critique of pure reason. trans. by Paul Guyer & A. W. Wood. Cambridge University press.##
Kemp Smith, N. (1962) A commentary to Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. New York: Humanities press##
Paton, H. J. (1961). Kant's metaphysic of experience. New York: MacMillan.##
Scruton, R. (1998) Kant. Oxford University press.##